Monday, October 03, 2011

A question and comment for Tim Hudak and the people who want to vote for him

Hi Tim. 

I'm curious about your platform. As I see it, if prisoners are going to be doing jobs that are normally done by municipal workers, while the PCs intend to shrink the public service, then the PC platform will raise the unemployment rate as many jobs will be lost.

The idea that employers will lay people off because of "higher taxes" is simply wrong. Are you trying to say that, for example, the Ford Motor Company will stop selling cars in Canada if we return the corporate tax rate to 1990s levels; they'll just pack up and go home? Nonsense. Corporations will remain operating in Canada so long as their product or service is profitable. However, the corporate tax rate only positively affects their profitability. Corporations pass their higher taxes along to the consumer in terms of higher prices. Higher prices do lessen demand for the product slightly, but corporations have mitigated the loss through higher revenue. Companies do not lay people off because of a tax hike, because such would affect their productivity negatively. They would not then be able to "bounce back" with improved market conditions, nor would they be able to react to the actions of their market competition.

Furthermore, numerous studies have already looked at the link between tax rates and employment and have determined that there is no statistical correlation. Taxes go up, employment stays about the same; taxes go down, employment stays about the same. 

The idea that tax cuts lead to job growth has also been demonstrated as false, using market principles. If I build bikes at my factory, I will hire employees when I need more bikes to be built for customers. More bikes will be built when demand for bikes is higher. As a corporate tax cut does nothing to stimulate demand for the product, my company will not sell more bikes. Instead, the tax cut will allow me to be more profitable. As a consequence, my business will not invest these profits into new hires, as I am not selling more bikes than I used to be selling. In fact, there are costs associated with overproduction, as well (warehousing, etc). Unless demand for bikes increases, my business will not hire a new employee. And with so many people newly unemployed by the loss of public sector jobs, there will be fewer people able to purcahse my bike, which translates into lower demand for my bikes. 

Allowing small businesses to be more profitable stimulates the broader econnomy by provoking more money to be spent local to the business (ie: in Ontario); in other words, small business people tend to spend their profits on goods and services in their communities. However, such does not occur when tax breaks are given to larger and multinational enterprises. Their profitability gains realized through tax cuts manifest as shareholder dividends, the vast majority of which are international in nature. Such money is not likely to be spent in Canada, let alone Ontario. 

In reality, once the corporate tax rate is competitive with other jurisdictions, further corporate tax cuts simply add to corporate profitability at the expense of revenues needed for social services and governmental programs. This process has been demonstrated time and time again over the course of the last fifty years. Canada currently has the same corporate tax rate as many "third-world" resource exporting countries, and Ontario is also exceptionally competitive with competing jurisdictions. In fact, it's the lowest tax rate of any developed industrial nation. Surely, as corporate tax cuts do little to stimulate the consumer economy, they do not need to go any lower.

So my question is the following: since corporate tax cuts will not magically produce jobs, what do you intend to do to keep Canadians -- especially the tens of thousands of public sector employees you plan on reducing -- working and paying taxes?

Wednesday, September 07, 2011

Open letter to Andrea Horwath and the Ontario New Democratic Party

Dear Andrea Horwath and the Ontario New Democratic Party,

I have just watched your first television spot presenting the NDP election platform, and am as a result seriously concerned with the direction the party is taking. In the ad Andrea talks about removing HST from a few essential services and products. Frankly, it appears as though a significant amount of the NDP campaign is based around this idea of giving back a few dollars in HST to working families. Such is indeed a noble effort, but you are guaranteed to lose this election based on that platform.

                It is certainly true that many families would benefit from the HST cut and, since the NDP philosophically orients itself with a strong middle-class, support for such policy would seem logical enough. However, Tim Hudak has centred his platform on middle-class tax cuts such as the exact HST exemption proposed by the NDP, and the Federal Conservatives have already lowered taxes for some working families.  Furthermore, regardless of whether it is objectively “true” or not the latent public discourse and awareness around Canadian political candidates – this narrative in which for most Canadians the political game is played between teams with distinct characteristics: namely that NDP candidates focus on social programs (because they don’t understand numbers) while the Conservatives focus on tax cuts (because they don’t understand culture) – ensures that many (if you like, “swing”) voters who want tax cuts will vote PC. In effect, by aligning the election platform almost exclusively on tax cuts, the NDP will be donating free advertising and support to the Conservative campaign. Many voters will interpret this “new” NDP position on taxes as an attempt to pander to them to buy their votes (even while simultaneously supporting the Conservatives for pandering to them in the same way, and even while liking Jack Layton as a person, etc...). As such, if you focus on the HST cuts for working families you will lose this election, and by extension so will working families.

                Instead of small dollar items, the NDP should focus on a long-term issue with real importance to working families, and indeed to the economic and social strength of the province and country as a whole. Beginning next year, the provinces will be renegotiating the health-care funding accords with the federal government. It is clear that the federal and provincial Conservative parties will speak about protecting health care while progressively removing its funding. This is the message that the NDP needs to get into their platform and their advertising campaign: “Who do you trust with health care: the party which supports corporate tax cuts or the party which invented public health care?”

Certainly the NDP has followed such a mantra in previous elections, to mixed reception. However, as your policy folks are well aware, a number of studies have been completed over the last ten years or so which empirically demonstrate the economic value of publically-funded health care. Typically, an explanation of the benefits of health care delivered as a public service, and perhaps more importantly as a representation of public wealth, requires a long conversation. Such long conversations are increasingly impossible within mainstream “consumer” electronic media, for a variety of reasons. It is very easy for conservative ideologies to be summarized in few words: “I don’t want to pay for it.” These words, while not new, have come to dominate political discourse right now, to the extent that the voters of Toronto voted in a complete liar in Rob Ford. Ford’s policies had no chance of being even remotely possible or even rational, and yet he won the election because people are desperate for hope, a public sentiment which the Ford campaign manipulated for victory. Rational minds can ineffectively fuss and fume all they want about the decline of democracy, as even when voters know that a candidate is lying, they will often support the idea behind “I don’t want to pay for it.” Perhaps this attitude is a result of everyone being nervous about their own economic situation, as many people continue to live in the 2008 recession and do not see many opportunities for recovery in their near-future. The trick for the NDP is that the party has to convince voters that certain public systems such as health-care and education are worth paying for. You will need to do this, or you will lose the upcoming election.

                So it is with this letter that I propose new words for the New Democratic Party, words which suggest hope and optimism which is so desperately needed and so easily manipulated, while simultaneously invoking the economic pragmatism so essential in these times. “Health Care Works” – simple, short, memorable, and a good entry point into a longer conversation about how public health care keeps families working in times of both hardship and success. Health care works because large employers such as Toyota have chosen Ontario precisely because of the social benefits of public health care and education. Public wealth makes better workers. Surely your strategists already know this. Even when they intend to actually cut taxes, the NDP is the party of health care, not tax cuts.

Regards,

Tuesday, August 23, 2011

open letter to Christie Blatchford of the National Post

‎Hi Christie,

While it is currently rather late in the evening, I just read your article in today's post and felt the need to respond. Not to the content of your article, which demonstrates that you are more of an opportunistic person than the deathbed Layton whom you set up as a martyr for the left. Such would prove an obvious and unnecessary reply to your writing, and I am sure that your email is currently overflowing with spectacularly colourful words indicating support for Mr. Layton in opposition to your inane prattle. Rather I am asking about the point of your words and the meaning behind them, beyond simply your paycheque.

Public figures have public deaths. Mr. Layton's was not unduly spectacular. Instead of simply letting the matter go, and writing about something more important than your own politics, you have positioned an argument based on a view that media coverage is the sole public. Other than a Liberal MP, no "normal citizens" are quoted. If you had done so, their words would indicate that they went about their unspectacular days unspectacularly. Surely you understand that the media organizations are fueled by viewership which translates into advertiser revenue, and the (unexpected) death of a notable public figure will often receive a full day of coverage on the news networks, with other stories being relayed by means of text crawlers or news highlights.

Surely you watch enough television to understand the limits of news broadcasting relative to the "hot story". To be frank, your paltry analysis of the public and/or media is limited to the CBC and Stephen Harper and is, as such, a complete joke. The tone of your words, on the other hand, is far from humorous. Your article is at best a rather selfish attempt to diffuse what conservatives often accuse as a weak and irrational emotion: the bleeding heart. Don't cry for Jack, you say. He's a schemer.

Frankly, not specifically to speak to the blackness of your kettle, but your pose around the funeral casket demonstrates that greed truly is the virtue of the damned. Unlike most of the people who have or are about to email you, I don't want you to go fuck yourself or anything, but if you aren't a better person than suggested by your opportunistic article, perhaps you had better go do that.

PS: I agree that Jean Chrétien was a bit of a douchebag today, but that's why you focus your nonsense on him rather than take a shot at a cancer patient.

Regards,

Wednesday, July 27, 2011

leftist distractions...

so, "leftists"...

we're in the middle of losing every political fight right now. rational discourse no longer works because we all need to take time to speak; money talks because money can walk away very quickly and still be heard. labour is increasingly siding with the "jobs first" mentality. "creative" protests are often creatively bankrupt and backfire in the media. the rights and hopes (and the hope for rights) of citizens increasingly adhere to market principles. the bankers are getting their way with the dissolution of public institutions in north america. workers overwhelmingly support these changes as an excuse to lower their taxes which, because they lack the means to invest and be called a shareholder (the only vote that matters these days), is now the only way for them to get a raise. meanwhile, leftist activists are focusing on environmental band-aids, pot legalization, and the cleansing of words...

in an era when protest and resistance are encouraged in order to justify law enforcement and we all want success in life, do we have any ideas left?

Friday, April 22, 2011

politics is not the time for team sports



For a game with such grand significance, politics sure is complicated isn’t it? Here we are with another election and our five teams have taken the field. Do you support red, orange, green, french, or blue?

In the various media, we hear opinions about who we should support and how doing so will serve the greater good of the country. Most of what is expressed avoids rational argument in favour of emotional commitment. However, one message particular to this election is often discussed in the popular media, although the significance remains debatable. In this capacity, I join the chorus of dissent against the governance of the Progressive Conservative party. Under Harper’s leadership, the foundation of the Conservative ideology has shifted. The party has gone from attempting to maintain the fiscal and operational integrity of Canadian institutions to one which in attempting to pass ideologically-motivated legislation seeks to undermine those very same institutions.

Despite the numerous controversies which Conservative actions have created, I have noticed a disturbing rhetorical trend in conversations with friends and acquaintances who are planning to support the Conservatives on May 2. Usually the debate will begin when I question them as to why they want to vote for their Conservative MP. The answer they provide is always about Stephen Harper. He’s better than the other leaders, they say. I’ll point out that Conservative policies have entirely betrayed the fiscal responsibility which the Conservatives unwaveringly champion. Some of the Conservative supporters to whom I speak recognize this problem. They also frequently disagree with the social, environmental, foreign-affairs, law enforcement, and human rights policies which the Conservatives have promoted or legislated for over the last five years.

Invariably, I am saddened at the end of our chat. After I have presented – to the best of my graduate-school-trained abilities – rational, empirical data which proves with little doubt that what the Conservatives say about their position on the economy or health care or crime is wrong, supporters will respond “Ya, I know. But I can vote Conservative without supporting all of their beliefs. It’s important to show your support. And anyway, our leader is better than yours.” Fuck, here we go.

Politics is different from sports, where faith unsupported by reason has no consequence. Let’s say that you are a Leafs fan. Year after year you pour money, time, and tears into your team they still end up one of the worst teams in the league. Fans are clearly being gouged with high ticket prices while the owners and management enjoy the massive financial success of the team. Regardless of data which clearly demonstrates the futility your remaining a fan, you will likely continue to support the team. Frankly, nothing really that bad happen in the world when a shitty sports team being supported. After all, at the end of the day it’s just a game on TV. Even when the Leafs play terribly year after year and show little interest in improving their game in order to provide their cheering fans with actual results, you can hold your head up high and say “The Leafs are the best team in the league.” No harm, no foul.

With politics, another game is being played, even though like hockey it is largely a phenomenon of television. If a shitty political party maintains its support, then harm will in fact be done. Under the Conservatives, for example, institutions will likely disappear in the name of “cutting the fat” and “reducing taxes”. The cost of living will raise for the poor and the middle-class, while the services available to them decline or disappear. Pubic wealth represented by institutions such as education and health care will be diminished while private wealth will be enriched as corporations take over governmental services and raise prices to generate profits.

It is a predictable irony that a government in the age of transparency demands the privilege to conceal itself from the public, and one which should not be tolerated. History has taught that such privacy is the endgame for morality in governance. Frankly, it’s time to stop supporting the notion of a singular prime minister leading the country to greatness. Canada is a Parliamentary democracy, not a Prime Ministerial one. By this I certainly don’t mean to diminish the office of the Prime Minister. I mean to suggest that there is an element to Quebec politics that all of Canada needs to learn. Quebec tends to elect strong parliamentary representatives to represent their interests in parliament. It is time for Canadians across this country to support their parliamentary officials, and not listen to any Prime Minister who views parliament with contempt. If this means that you honestly vote Conservative, fine. But know that the Conservatives have demonstrated that won’t play with parliament and that they find the opinions of Canadians as represented by the politicians to be irreleant to governance.

Monday, February 07, 2011

O/H @ whatnext? festival


O/H @ whatnext? festival from Quintin Hewlett on Vimeo.


O/H (Christina Sealey, Richard Oddie, David Foster)

Christ's Church Cathedral, Hamilton
Saturday, February 5, 2011
presented by New Harbours Music Series and Hamilton Philharmonic Orchestra

ambient sound + lighting, beer. p + c O/H, qzh, Throwaway Digital 2011

Tuesday, January 18, 2011

theorizing time and the social network

fellow scholars, let's think socially

over the past few platform updates, it appears to my eyes that FB can increasingly be seen to push for "immediacy". they seem to want to make the history of one's activity on FB increasingly obscure. i can only hypothesize that such is the monetization of FB -- in twenty years, people will have to purchase their photo albums and diary-like conversations from the FB company in neatly-packaged and reasonably-priced retail packages. all of that free content provided by users will be sold back to them as the nostalgia they so desperately need.

i'm thinking about time, money as the guardian of "en recherche du temps perdu", and the digital network

am i just mad because i can't find my links, or is there something about how Facebook is monetizing our identity that needs to be critically vocalized?

Thursday, December 23, 2010

a response to Marshall McLuhan's Understanding Media

After the publication of Understanding Media in 1964, Marshall McLuhan became for a while perhaps the most famous North American thinker. His fame was likely due to his use of memorable slogans which distilled his beliefs to what in the television industry is termed a ‘catch-phrase’. It is within these terms that McLuhan is best understood. While this paper intends to summarise rather than critique McLuhan’s thinking, I will suggest a few concerns which I will later examine in greater detail in the final term paper.

Perhaps the most egregious and obvious fault of the text is McLuhan’s continual use of broad generalizations when providing examples to support his arguments. This tendency is most notable, and perhaps the least excusable, when McLuhan describes human characteristics and subjective positions as contingent with national identity. One can piece together a list of national characteristics to which McLuhan alludes throughout his text, for example: “The African insistence on group participation and on chanting and shouting during films...” (287); “the Eskimo no more needs to look at a picture right side up...” (191), or the numerous references to “the American”, “the Russian”, and “the Chinese”. However, McLuhan’s naive essentialisms should not be dismissed out of hand by a reader schooled in contemporary identity politics. His Platonic appeal to the universal forms of being Chinese, African, or otherwise can be used if placed into their proper context. When speaking about the manner in which non-literate peoples come to understand and experience photography and motion images, for example, a critic may use McLuhan’s point about the non-linear reading strategies employed by the non-literate person without reference to a national or ethnic tradition. Perhaps more optimistically, McLuhan’s use of essentialised national characteristics can be forgiven as a rhetorical device consistent with a society enmeshed in what can perhaps be described as the essentializing zeitgeist of the Cold War. In any case, such criticisms will presently be glossed in favour of their more detailed return in a future paper.

Not simply a catalogue of the various extant media, McLuhan suggests that media should be understood as a multitude of extensions of the human body. Fundamentally, he positions media as the principle manner in which the production and consumption of knowledge occurs, as determined by its expression through a technological practise. Different subject positions in the human condition can as a consequence be understood as having been produced relative to the material availability of media.

It is here that we can begin to forgive McLuhan for his essentialised national categories. “The African...”, for example, is not rendered lesser than “the North American” due to any racial or cultural features inherent to the people of the nations of Africa. Rather, when seen within the context of the historical development of both film and colonial practices, it is perfectly understandable that McLuhan should want to describe what he felt was the most likely subjective position for a person born in a society lacking access to highly technological media as “the Eskimo” or “the African”. It is the job of the contemporary scholar working with McLuhan’s ideas to understand that the national identities used by the author are convenient historical constructions and, as a consequence, to determine a more precise and flexible body of examples of different subjectivities produced by differing literacy in relation to highly technological media.

McLuhan focuses his concern on the changes to human subjectivity which have resulted from the development of electric technologies. Electricity renders the transmission and experience of information instantaneous, and as such a new degree of politics has emerged: “Electric speed in bringing all social and political functions together in a sudden implosion has heightened human awareness of responsibility to an intense degree. It is this implosive factor that alters the position of the Negro, the teen-ager, and some other groups. They can no longer be contained, in the political sense of limited association. They are now involved in our lives, as we in theirs, thanks to the electric media. ... The mark of our time is its revulsions against imposed patterns. We are suddenly eager to have things and people declare their beings totally.” (5) McLuhan’s notion of media therefore disturbs the uniqueness of external reality relative to human subjectivity. What were once objects and events rationalised as exterior entities and processes capable of receiving human agency – indeed knowledge itself – have suddenly been interiorised as extensions of the human body itself. The capacity of a subject to understand and express their existence in the world is markedly different when that subject exists within a society mobilised by electricity. Indeed, the body itself is continually involved in a process of adaptation to such ‘mutation’: "Any invention or technology is an extension or self-amputation of our physical bodies, and such extension also demands new ratios or new equilibriums among the other organs and extensions of the body." (45)

Through an interrogation of the technologies of writing and print, McLuhan demonstrates that human existence is determined by technical processes of expression. Before electricity, existence was ordered along in the framework of print, a linear and sequential process which allowed a great and rapid dissemination of both books and a new world view contingent on alphanumeric literacy. McLuhan argues that this capacity for linear order shaped human use of other technologies: "Only alphabetic cultures have ever mastered connected lineal sequences as pervasive forms of psychic and social organization. The breaking up of every kind of experience into uniform units in order to produce faster action and change of form (applied knowledge) has been the secret of Western power over man and nature alike.” (85) Thus, he is able to rationalise the militarism which dominated the twentieth century: “our Western industrial programs have quite involuntarily been so militant, and our military programs have been so industrial. Both are shaped by the alphabet in their technique of transformation and control by making all situations uniform and continuous."

Electricity is a revolutionary technology due to the fact that its instantaneous nature disrupts continuity and centralised power (and by extension, discourse).

One can begin to critique McLuhan with his distinction between hot and cold media, characterised as either hot, which are constituted by what he refers to as information presented to one or a number of senses with a high degree of depth (definition), or cold, which present information in a less defined manner. While in both cases audiences participate in their own understanding of the message being conveyed, hot media invite a low amount of audience participation, while for cold media the reverse is true. Fundamentally, the categories which he uses are too essentialising: "A hot medium is one that extends one single sense in 'high definition' High definition is the state of being well filled with data. A photograph is, visually, 'high definition.' A cartoon is 'low definition' simply because very little visual information is provided." (22) While the conception of hot and cold may each be useful, media do not unify into a coherent entity as McLuhan suggests by "a photograph is" or "a cartoon is". Minimalist photographers such as Hiroshi Sugimoto allow for McLuhan's definition of low definition, while 'cartoon' artists such as Frank Miller, Gerhard and Dave Sim, Boris Vallejo, and many among the great number of Japanese artists who work in the Manga form attest to the potential for a high definition comic book. Furthermore, it is possible to suggest that given sufficient time to mature, audiences can be seen as increasingly active media participants.


Notes

1.  See also The Medium is the Massage: “The older, traditional ideas of private, isolated thoughts and                actions – the patterns of mechanistic technologies – are very seriously threatened by new methods of            instantaneous electric information retrieval” (12).

2.  Nietzsche’s conception of will to power is perhaps a more accurate phrase to replace the term                      ‘existence’ in this context.

Thursday, November 25, 2010

Francis Bacon and Augustus Comte -- notes

One of the principles of Renaissance thought was the liberation of the human subject from the limitations of authority and tradition, of which the church was perhaps the most significant influence. Francis Bacon was one of the chief proponents of what was later understood as humanism. Fundamentally, Bacon’s thought was centred upon the idea that human ingenuity and discovery was a reflection of the will and grace of God. Indeed, the hand of God was working through human invention. Scientific progress is a reflection of a divine sense of the good; as such, it flourishes during times of peace (which Bacon incorrectly points out was extant at the time of his writing). To this end, in Thoughts and Conclusions on the Interpretation of Nature as a Science Productive of Works he outlines the benefits conferred by three technologies which he considers to be representative for the triumph of human ingenuity over the natural processes which limit the human subject: printing, gunpowder, and the magnetic compass. Through a description of these inventions, Bacon seeks to establish the importance of the process of invention to human existence. Of cardinal significance is the notion that the acquisition of knowledge serves to improve one’s potential for acting well within world affairs, as “the improvement of man’s mind and the improvement of man’s lot are one and the same thing” (27).

Importantly, the development of the individual human subject is seen as key to the development of the body politic. Bacon suggests that scientific invention is among the most beneficial of human activities, “for the benefits inventors confer extend to the whole human race” (26). To a modern reader aware of the history and politics of European colonialism, it is difficult to avoid noting the political economy of this statement, which was written by a member of the English aristocracy who was then serving as a senior governmental bureaucrat at a time of colonial expansion. Of course, by stressing the importance of the compass, Bacon writes that England’s colonial enterprises were themselves reflections of the realisation of power through scientific processes. Through the acquisition of knowledge and the continuation of technological invention, mankind (to use Bacon’s notably gendered language) is able to expand the possibilities for action and self-realisation. In his Novum Organum, he writes that “knowledge and human power come to the same thing, for where the cause is not known the effect cannot be produced” (29). Much like Plato’s explanation of how leaders must understand the good in order to understand the earthly manifestation of forms, Bacon suggests that mankind will understand the truth only by avoiding what he terms the false idols of intellectual activity – Idols of the Tribe, in which perception is a human affair which “distorts and corrupts the nature of things by mingling its own nature with it” (29); Idols of the Cave, wherein Bacon adapts Plato’s Cave analogy to argue that an individual person’s traits and personality may distort an understanding of reality; Idols of the Market-place, which emerge from the relational dynamics inherent to human subjectivity, manifest in language: “Words plainly do violence to the understanding and throw everything into confusion, and lead men into innumerable empty controversies and fictions” (30); and Idols of the Theatre, the dogmas associated with established philosophy, “which have become established through tradition, credulity and neglect” (30). By means of the truth, mankind will master the self. Indeed, determined effort “devoted to sane and solid purposes could triumph over every obstacle” (28). Furthermore, “inventions come without force or disturbance ... while civil changes rarely proceed without uproar and violence” (26). On the Idols and on the Scientific Study of Nature invokes Augustine’s City of God in positing a fantastic and perfectly ordered geography of thought, with all of the various sciences operating in harmony.

In order to realise the benefits of scientific progress, Bacon calls for an examination of the methods of inquiry. Throughout most of late antiquity and the medieval period, intellectual activity first involved accepting the established authority and supplementing it with opinion. The philosophical tradition then allowed for knowledge to be produced by means of dialectics, which “look only for logical consistency” (25). Lastly, experiential data allowed for some intellectual discovery, but only by means of happenstance, not methodological rigour. To counter such trends, and to account for the fact that chance is a significant contributor to intellectual discovery, a rigorous method of scientific inquiry is required. Bacon proposed in On the Reformation of Education that the education systems then extant in Europe were insufficient for such a task. He complains that education can be seen to “have rather augmented the number of learned men than raised and rectifies the sciences themselves” (34), and furthermore that “this dedication of colleges and societies to the use only of professory learning has not only been inimical to the growth of the sciences, but has also been prejudicial to states and government” (35). Bacon thus suggests that universities be equipped with the latest laboratory and observational equipment, that universities across Europe need to network with each other to allow the sciences to flourish outside of geographical happenstance, that the salaries of Lecturers (those who research “Philosophy” and “Universality”) must be sufficient to allow the best minds to seek such a life pursuit, as lecturers “are as it were the keepers and guardians of the whole store and provision of learning” (35), and finally that logic and rhetoric, the two disciplines foundational to all intellectual activity, should be reserved for mature and sufficiently-developed minds. It is quite interesting to note retroactively that such complaints have often been levelled at universities, and the desire to reform education to the benefit of the liberated human subject has been rejuvenated in a time when corporate and business interests have proliferated, and arguably poisoned, the integrity of the pursuit of knowledge.

Humanism had become entrenched in European consciousness by the time Augustus Comte was writing about scientific progress in The Nature and Importance of the Positive Philosophy. Comte believes that a historical overview is necessary, “for no idea can be properly understood apart from its history” (45). He then seeks to systematise the development of thought by stating “that each branch of our knowledge, passes in succession through three theoretical states: the theological or fictitious state, the metaphysical or abstract state, and the scientific or positive state”. As a consequence, three methods for the pursuit of knowledge come to the fore: the theological method, which situates all phenomena as originating with divine influence; the metaphysical method, in which “the supernatural agents are replaced by abstract forces, real entities or personified abstractions” which are themselves in turn the originators of all phenomena; and the positive method, which recognizes “the impossibility of of obtaining absolute truth” and therefore “endeavours ... to discover, by a well-combined use of reasoning and observation, the actual laws of phenomena – that is to say, their invariable relations of succession and likeness”. Comte demonstrates an interesting self-awareness when he describes “the need at every epoch of having some theory to connect the facts” (46). His thinking is an extension of Bacon’s idea that the knowledge of reality must in principle come from observed phenomena. Thus, “it is no less true that, in order to observe, our mind has need of some theory or other”. However, in order to objectively navigate the near-infinite number of subjective understandings, observation of phenomena must be methodologically rigorous in order to properly understand both the self and the ‘truth’ that results from intellectual activity, for “it is experience alone which has enabled us to estimate our abilities rightly” (47).

It is to this end that he outlines the necessity of the positive philosophy, whose “fundamental character ... is to consider all phenomena as subject to invariable natural laws. The exact discovery of these laws and their reduction to the least possible number constitute the goal of all our efforts; for we regard the search after what are called causes, whether first or final, as absolutely inaccessible and unmeaning” (48). In this capacity, he rejects the metaphysical and theological arguments around the interpretation and realisation of divine will. In reductionist terms, everything necessary for the understanding of a given phenomenon is present within the phenomenon itself. The remainder of the chapter sketches “what stage in the formation of that philosophy has now been reached and what remains to be done in order to constitute it fully” (49). He argues that the pursuit of knowledge was rendered contingent with positivism first among the most simple and general of disciplines, as “astronomical phenomena ... were the first to be subjected to positive theories”, followed by a succession of physical sciences increasingly proximal to the human subject. This process originated with Aristotelian thinking and has taken place “continuously and at an increasing rate”. Comte recognizes that positive theories have not been adapted to the study of all phenomena, and there remains a great deal of research to be accomplished and a “gap” which must be bridged, as positive theories must be utilized in order to understand the dynamics of “social physics” (50).

The important dynamic inherent to Comte’s thinking is the reduction of different systems of thought to the same process of knowledge production, for when “our fundamental conceptions [have] thus been rendered homogeneous, philosophy will be consituted finally in the positive state,” at which point all theological and metaphysical methodologies and systems of thought will be rendered obsolete.The individual disciplines of scientific inquiry become established when they have “developed far enough to admit of separate cultivation – that is to say, when it has arrived at a stage in which it is capable of constituting the sole pursuit of certain minds” (51). Indeed, positivism has developed rather continuously since Bacon, to the point where Comte wishes to prove that “direct contemplation of the mind by itself is a pure illusion” (53), as the functioning of the brain is only observable from an objective position. Of course, Comte was not to live to see the developments in medical imaging technologies, which have indeed allowed the discipline of neuroscience to investigate the machinations of the brain in self-aware subjects. More provocatively, however, it is possible to interpret Comte’s statement that “interior observation gives rise to almost as many divergent opinions as there are so-called observers” (53) as prognosticating the development of psychoanalysis (which is of course one of the missing positive “social sciences”).

While Comte sates that the ancients were able to participate with significant contributions in numerous areas of scientific thought, due to the relatively immature state of their development, “it is ... impossible not to be struck by the great inconveniences which [the division into disciplines] produces.” He argues for the creation of an executive body given the task of providing an overview of the processes of each scientific discipline “to determine exactly the character of each science, to discover the relations and concatenation of the sciences, and to reduce, if possible, all their chief principles to the smallest number of common principles” (52). Scientists should be trained to have a general understanding of science before specializing. Furthermore, Comte calls for the creation of “a specific class on men, whose special and permanent function would consist in connecting each new special discovery with the general system”. To explain such a function, he emphasizes that understanding is essentially a singular discipline, and that the divisions of understanding into disciplines is an artificial principle which “by separating the difficulties, resolve[s] them more easily” (55). However, these distinctions can serve problematic when “questions arise which need to be treated by combining the points of view of several sciences”.

Comte states that positivism is the only ideological system which can be seen to be in ascent; the others have been in decline for centuries. This process will be completed once positivism has included the study of social phenomena, and furthermore that it is understood as a single and coherent theory which encompasses all of the disciplines of thought. When such has been accomplished, “the revolutionary crisis which harasses civilised people will then be at an end” (57). He concludes this section by stating that the endeavour to synthesize the various disciplines of human inquiry is not to reduce their variables to “one sole law”.  Fundamentally, the human mind is not able to realize perfection, which would be required for a valid and objective “sole law” for the understanding of all phenomena: “the resources of the human mind are too feeble, and the universe is too complicated, to admit of our ever attaining such scientific perfection”. In this context, it is interesting to note that Comte hints at the ‘holy grail’ of physics after Einstein, namely the unified field theory which seeks to harmonize theories of the macro universe (astronomy) with those concerned with the subatomic universe: “it seems to me that we could hope to arrive at it only by connecting all natural phenomena with the most general positive law with which we are acquainted – the law of gravitation – which already links all astronomical phenomena to some of the phenomena of terrestrial physics” (58). While dismissed by scholars and scientists of most disciplines, the quest for such unity remains at the heart of theoretical physics.

Borgman, Feenberg, and Heidegger: notes toward a possible dialogue

In order to examine the nature of existence within the framework of the multiple subjectivities produced by technology, Heidegger sought to essentialize the relationship between human subject and technology by means of an examination, in reductive terms, of that which is “not technological”. In the question concerning technology, Heidegger provided a framework for the understanding of technology as a means by which the production of meaning involves the ordering of reality into resources ordered and viewed as always-already on stand-by for their exploitation. While technology does indeed have the capacity for disclosure, ultimately Heidegger rejects technology as lacking the capacity for achieving the “good life” in which freedom of choice defines the subject.

         Borgmann responded to Heidegger’s negative critique of technology by means of trying to understand the capacity of technological processes to redefine the human subject. Fundamentally, he implicitly rejects Heidegger’s conception of a unified subject, which, will historically-determined, speaks with one pretechnological voice. To this end, he defines the subject in relation to that which objectivizes. Objects and practices can be seen as particular means of focus. “A focal practice is the resolute and regular dedication to a focal thing. ... [They] are at ease with the natural sciences.” focal things “are concrete, tangible, and deep, admitting of no functional equivalents; they have a tradition, structure, and rhythm of their own. They are unprocurable and finally beyond our control.” (307) focus is itself identified by means of an etymological investigation into the word as both hearth and "optical or geometric" instrument. "a focus gathers the relations of its context and radiates into its surroundings and informs them" (293-4). "to focus on something or to bring it into focus is to make it central, clear, and articulate> It is in the context of these historical and living senses of "focus" that I want to speak of focal things and practices." (294)

          It is here that Borgmann breaks with Heidegger, for he questions whether art is in fact the sole means (or focus) by which authentic disclosures can be realised. that humans look to their environment is entirely natural: "The wildernes is beyond the procurement of technology, and our response to it takes us past consumption. But it also teaches us to accept and appropriate technology" (296). Borgmann then looks at two such practices: competitive running, and the "culture of the table", in order to elaborate the notion that focal events can be mistakenly construed as "experiences in the subjective sense, events that have their real meaning in transporting a person into a certain mental or emotional state". Technology will then endeavour to more efficiently deliver and replace the state with itself, unless "we guard focal things in their depth and integrity". "To elaborate the context of focal events is to grant them their proper eloquence." (297)

          Technology comes to be realised as a process of subjective alienation due to the fact that by means of the storing of labour through time, the subject it divided against itself: satisfaction of desire and the realisation of satisfaction are rendered discontinuous. "I am a divided person; my achievement lies in the past, my enjoyment in the present." (297) Borgmann then describes the alienating experience of industrial food, which replaces the culture of the table. "eating in a focal setting differs sharply from the social and cultural anonymity of a fast-food outlet." (299). and yet, these small, seemingly mundane practices attain a degree of Benjaminian aura precisely due to their recontextualization within the technological apparatus of the modern era. “On the spur of the moment, we normally act out what has been nurtured in our daily practices as they have been shaped by the norms of our time.” (300).

         While ritual was the social means by which practices became tradition in ancient societies, for modern humans engaged in the technological process, what comes to be known as the device paradigm (in the next section) is defined: devices realize increasing efficiencies which realize states of satisfied desire. Heidegger’s critique here stands, for the creation and satisfaction of desires will itself become an autonomous and self-perpetuating process under the rule of technology. Borgmann: “If we are to challenge the rule of technology, we can only do so through the practice of engagement. ... without a practice an engaging action or event can momentarily light up our life, but it cannot order and orient it focally. Through a practice we are able to accomplish what remains unattainable through a series of individual decisions and acts.” (300)

         Borgmann posits that making “the technological universe hospitable to focal things turns out to be the heart of the reform of technology …. [for] only things that we experience as greater and other than ourselves can move us to judge and change technology in the first place” (302). And so we come to the redemptive potential inherent to technology in Borgmann’s thought. Fundamentally, what we can describe as the “good life” requires the application of our capacity for engaging with a self-defined subjective experience. engagement encompasses “the acquisition of skills, the fidelity to a daily discipline, the broadening of sensibility, the profound interaction of human beings, and the preservation and development of tradition” (304), and in the process “harmonize the variety among people but also within the life of one person”. 

         However, focal things can also subsume a person and take over the definition of the good life, which involves the mastery of the capacity to master a practice and thus a means of ordering and understanding. While not in itself either absolute or an absolution, “it is not finally decisive whether and how we succeed in securing an ordered and excellent life for worldlessly conceived subjects” (307), there remains the possibility that “a technological device or, more generally, a technological invention may someday address us as such a thing, one that, whatever its genesis, has taken on a character of its own, that challenges and fulfills us, that centres and illuminates our world?” At this point, Borgmann, surmises, technology would itself be able to “birth ... a focal thing or event”
>> 
“the reform of technology .... must be one of and not merely one within the device paradigm. ... A reform of the paradigm is ... the recognition and the restraint of the paradigm. To restrain the paradigm is to restrict it to its proper sphere. Its proper sphere is the background or periphery of focal things and practices. ... Reform must make room for focal things and practices.” (308) thus, the good inherent to a focal thing or pratice will result in ends which resonate with the means of their procural, hence the story of the environmentally-conscious runner on page 309. “To have a focal thing radiate transformatively into its environment is not to exact some kind of service from it but to grant it its proper eloquence.”
 <<
Borgmann therefore suggests that people should balance the political consequences of tehcnological enthrallment with the fact that “in one or another area of one’s life one should gratefully accept the disburdenment from daily and time-consuming chores and allow celebration and world citizenship to prosper in the time that has been gained.” (310). The good life involves a degree of social recognition for having mastered an area of focal practice, for being able to share the celebratory moments of life and success with loved ones, and “where we encounter our fellow human beings in the fullness of their capacities, and where we know ourselves to be equal to that world in depth and strength.” (310). mastery of knowledge is simply mastery “of the means rather than the ends of life. What is needed if we are to make the world truly and finally ours again is the recovery of a centre and a standpoint from which one can tell what matters in the world and what merely clutters it up. A focal concern is that centre of orientation.” (311)

         The other two articles serve to position Heidegger and Borgmann in relation to each other, and in doing so they alternatively come to agree with one thinker or the other. Thus, we can witness Dreyfus and Spinosa’s article argues in support of Heidegger’s critique of technology being “a more cogherent and credible answer than Borgmann’s” (315). They state that for Heidegger, technology is a process in which ordering increasingly supplants objects themselves, which are themselves merely a means for further ordering. Borgmann is in agreement, to the extent that “the object disappears precisely to the extent that the subject gains total control”. And yet, in gaining control “the post-modern subject is reduced to a ‘point of arbitrary desires’” (316-7). Thus, despite the displacement of objects, (hyper)reality remains determined by the satisfaction of desire: “Heidegger’s intuition is that treating everything as standing reserve or, as we might say, resources, makes possible endless disaggregation, redistridution, and reaggregation for its own sake.” Along with the object, Dreyfus argues that Heidegger eliminates subjectivity. Technology is thus “a new stage in the understanding of being.” (317) “Thanks to Nietzsche, Heidegger could sense that, when everything becomes standing reserve or resources, people and things will no longer be understood as having essences or identities or, for people, the goal of satisfying arbitrary desires”. the new subject gains meaning not through fixity, but rather through the process of connection. “Even desireing subjects have been sucked up as standing reserve.” (319)

         For Heidegger, “when a focal event such as a family meal is working to the point where it has its particular integrity, one feels extraordinarily in tune with all that is happening, a special graceful ease takes over, and events seem to unfold of their own momentum” (320). When a “thing is thinging”, says Heidegger, the divinities must be present; focal practices channel the divine by means of mortality. “So long as a people who regularly encounter a thing are socialized to respond to it appropriately, their practices are organized around the thing, and its solicitations are taken into account even when no one notices” (320). Dreyfus agrees with Borgman’s rejection of Heidegger’s pretechnological focal things to be “misleading and dispiriting” (321).

         Dreyfus argues that groups of people use technologies adaptively and in social congruence (given congruent sociability)., and furthermore that given a phenomenological concern, the fact that humans can choose to exercise from a variety of possibilities, and thus express their mortality, determines that people are “never wholly a resource” (322). “Neither equipment nor roles could be gathered, but the skills for treating ourselves as disaggregated skills and the world as a series of open possibilities are what are drawn together so that vaious dispersed skillful performances become possible. But if we focus on the skills for dispersing alone, then the dangerous seduction of technology is enhanced.”
 <<
         “Resistance to technological practices by cultivating focal practices is the primary solution Borgmann gives to saving ourselves from technological devastation. ... Heidegger’s view of technology allows him to find a positive relation to it, but only so long as we maintain skills for disclosing other kinds of worlds. Freeing us from having a total fixed identity so that we may experience ourselves as multiple identities disclosing multiple worlds is what Heidegger calls technology’s saving power.” (323). Thus Dreyfus and Spinosa can come to terms with the two authors: “as mortal disclosers of worlds in the plural, the only integrity we can hope to achieve is our openness to dwelling in many worlds and the capacity to move among them. Only such a capacity allows us to accept Heidegger’s and Borgmann’s criticism of technology and still have Heidegger’s genuinely positive relationship to technological things.” (324)
>> 
Feenberg opens his article with the condemnation of Hedegger as an institutional force. . Such, however, is not a rejection of Heidegger, but rather a circumscription of meaning as plurality which is otherwise obscured by Heideggerian thought as having been furnished with an institutional status. And yet he can agree with Heidegger that “ Technology is a cultural form through which everything in the modern world becomes available for control. Technology thus violates both humanity and nature at a far deeper level than war and environmental destruction. To this culture of control corresponds an inflation of the subjectivity of the controller” (328)

          Feenberg states that “Heidegger’s critique of autonomous technology is not without merit” (329), and wonders whether “our specifically technological engagement with the world ... is merely an attitude or it it embedded in the actual design of modern technological devices?”. The former is contingent with the historical process itself, which contextualizes the production of meaning, while the latter Feenberg argues to be rather optimistic in its causal effectiveness. “Heidegger holds that the restructuring of social reality by technical action is inimical to a life rich in meaning.” (329). Feenberg states that for Borgmann, the logic of devices is to become increasingly efficient, which is defined by a replacement of expertise, resource gathering and exploitation, and social ritural by machine functionality. However, “the generalization of the device paradigm, its universal substitution for simpler ways, has a deadening effect. Where means and ends, contexts and commodities are strictly separated, life is drained of meaning. Individual involvement with nature and other human beings is reduced to a bare minimum, and possession and control become the highest values.” (330) 

[potential reading of Apple computers]

          Feenberg argues that Borgman “offers a more understandable response to invasive technology than anything in Heidegger”, as the former “[bounds] the technical sphere to restore the centrality of meaning” (330). for Borgmann, the modern human subject mediated by the computer becomes “disposable experiences that can be turned on and off like water from a faucet. The person as a focal thing has become a commodity delivered by a device”(331). Feenberg rejects Borgmann’s conception of computer-mediated communication for being naive and incomplete, for it rejects the possibilities for the development of human subjectivities enabled by communication otherwise impossible. “Borgmann’s critique of technology pursues the larger conenctions and social implications masked by the device paradigm. To this extent it is genuinely dereifying. But insofar as it fails to incorporate these hidden social dimensions into the concept of technology itself, it remains still partially caught in the very way of thinking it criticizes.” (332)

          Feenberg argues that Heidegger “is demanding that we recognize fully our own unsurpassable belonging to a world in which meaning guides the rituals that crystallize around things.” (333). “The fourfold refers to no particular system of practices and things, but reminds us of what all such systems have in common insofar as all human lives are rooted in enacted meaning of some sort” (333). “Is the gathering thing a node in a network? ... The notion o the thing as a gathering that discloses a world can be seen as a correective to the overemphasis on the role of Dasein in disclosure in [Being and Time]. There, world was defined not as “all that is”, nor as an object of knowledge, but as the realm of everyday practice.” (334) Feenberg thus posits Heidegger’s thought as circumscribed by its objectivist (managerial) nature.


(discussion of Schindler’s list as an unethical film)

Wednesday, November 17, 2010

talking on james street north, episode 4


talking on james street north, episode 4 from Quintin Hewlett on Vimeo.


In November of 2005, I formalised an informal talk amongst artists, writers, activists, and community organizers. Issues discussed included gentrification and economic development, the purpose of a life in and with art, the experiences of running an independent gallery, the politics of community, and the community of politics.

The participants for this episode are Jeremy Freiburger, Matt Jelly, Dane Pederson, Quintin Hewlett, Andrea Carvalho, Matt Teagel, Steve Mazza, and Gary Buttrum.

camera + sound, p + c = qzh 2005

Tuesday, November 16, 2010

talking on james street north, episode 3


talking on james street north, episode 3 from Quintin Hewlett on Vimeo.


In November of 2005, I formalised an informal talk amongst artists, writers, activists, and community organizers. Issues discussed included gentrification and economic development, the purpose of a life in and with art, the experiences of running an independent gallery, the politics of community, and the community of politics.

The participants for this episode are Jeremy Freiburger, Matt Jelly, Dane Pederson, Quintin Hewlett, Andrea Carvalho, Matt Teagel, Steve Mazza, and Gary Buttrum.

camera + sound, p + c = qzh 2005

Monday, November 15, 2010

talking on james street north, episode 2


talking on james street north, episode 2 from Quintin Hewlett on Vimeo.


In November of 2005, I formalised an informal talk amongst artists, writers, activists, and community organizers. Issues discussed included gentrification and economic development, the purpose of a life in and with art, the experiences of running an independent gallery, the politics of community, and the community of politics.

The participants for this episode are Jeremy Freiburger, Matt Jelly, Dane Pederson, Quintin Hewlett, Andrea Carvalho, Matt Teagel, Steve Mazza, and Gary Buttrum.

camera + sound, p + c = qzh 2005

Sunday, November 14, 2010

talking on james street north, episode 1


talking on james street north, episode 1 from Quintin Hewlett on Vimeo.


In November of 2005, I formalised an informal talk amongst artists, writers, activists, and community organizers. Issues discussed included gentrification and economic development, the purpose of a life in and with art, the experiences of running an independent gallery, the politics of community, and the community of politics.

The participants for this episode are Jeremy Freiburger, Matt Jelly, Dane Pederson, Quintin Hewlett, Andrea Carvalho, Matt Teagel, Steve Mazza, and Gary Buttrum.

camera + sound, p + c = qzh 2005

Monday, November 01, 2010

Francis Bacon and Augustus Comte -- notes

One of the principles of Renaissance thought was the liberation of the human subject from the limitations of authority and tradition, of which the church was perhaps the most significant influence. Francis Bacon was one of the chief proponents of what was later understood as humanism. Fundamentally, Bacon’s thought was centred upon the idea that human ingenuity and discovery was a reflection of the will and grace of God. Indeed, the hand of God was working through human invention. Scientific progress is a reflection of a divine sense of the good; as such, it flourishes during times of peace (which Bacon incorrectly points out was extant at the time of his writing). To this end, in Thoughts and Conclusions on the Interpretation of Nature as a Science Productive of Works he outlines the benefits conferred by three technologies which he considers to be representative for the triumph of human ingenuity over the natural processes which limit the human subject: printing, gunpowder, and the magnetic compass. Through a description of these inventions, Bacon seeks to establish the importance of the process of invention to human existence. Of cardinal significance is the notion that the acquisition of knowledge serves to improve one’s potential for acting well within world affairs, as “the improvement of man’s mind and the improvement of man’s lot are one and the same thing” (27).

Importantly, the development of the individual human subject is seen as key to the development of the body politic. Bacon suggests that scientific invention is among the most beneficial of human activities, “for the benefits inventors confer extend to the whole human race” (26). To a modern reader aware of the history and politics of European colonialism, it is difficult to avoid noting the political economy of this statement, which was written by a member of the English aristocracy who was then serving as a senior governmental bureaucrat at a time of colonial expansion. Of course, by stressing the importance of the compass, Bacon writes that England’s colonial enterprises were themselves reflections of the realisation of power through scientific processes. Through the acquisition of knowledge and the continuation of technological invention, mankind (to use Bacon’s notably gendered language) is able to expand the possibilities for action and self-realisation. In his Novum Organum, he writes that “knowledge and human power come to the same thing, for where the cause is not known the effect cannot be produced” (29). Much like Plato’s explanation of how leaders must understand the good in order to understand the earthly manifestation of forms, Bacon suggests that mankind will understand the truth only by avoiding what he terms the false idols of intellectual activity – Idols of the Tribe, in which perception is a human affair which “distorts and corrupts the nature of things by mingling its own nature with it” (29); Idols of the Cave, wherein Bacon adapts Plato’s Cave analogy to argue that an individual person’s traits and personality may distort an understanding of reality; Idols of the Market-place, which emerge from the relational dynamics inherent to human subjectivity, manifest in language: “Words plainly do violence to the understanding and throw everything into confusion, and lead men into innumerable empty controversies and fictions” (30); and Idols of the Theatre, the dogmas associated with established philosophy, “which have become established through tradition, credulity and neglect” (30). By means of the truth, mankind will master the self. Indeed, determined effort “devoted to sane and solid purposes could triumph over every obstacle” (28). Furthermore, “inventions come without force or disturbance ... while civil changes rarely proceed without uproar and violence” (26). On the Idols and on the Scientific Study of Nature invokes Augustine’s City of God in positing a fantastic and perfectly ordered geography of thought, with all of the various sciences operating in harmony.

In order to realise the benefits of scientific progress, Bacon calls for an examination of the methods of inquiry. Throughout most of late antiquity and the medieval period, intellectual activity first involved accepting the established authority and supplementing it with opinion. The philosophical tradition then allowed for knowledge to be produced by means of dialectics, which “look only for logical consistency” (25). Lastly, experiential data allowed for some intellectual discovery, but only by means of happenstance, not methodological rigour. To counter such trends, and to account for the fact that chance is a significant contributor to intellectual discovery, a rigorous method of scientific inquiry is required. Bacon proposed in On the Reformation of Education that the education systems then extant in Europe were insufficient for such a task. He complains that education can be seen to “have rather augmented the number of learned men than raised and rectifies the sciences themselves” (34), and furthermore that “this dedication of colleges and societies to the use only of professory learning has not only been inimical to the growth of the sciences, but has also been prejudicial to states and government” (35). Bacon thus suggests that universities be equipped with the latest laboratory and observational equipment, that universities across Europe need to network with each other to allow the sciences to flourish outside of geographical happenstance, that the salaries of Lecturers (those who research “Philosophy” and “Universality”) must be sufficient to allow the best minds to seek such a life pursuit, as lecturers “are as it were the keepers and guardians of the whole store and provision of learning” (35), and finally that logic and rhetoric, the two disciplines foundational to all intellectual activity, should be reserved for mature and sufficiently-developed minds. It is quite interesting to note retroactively that such complaints have often been levelled at universities, and the desire to reform education to the benefit of the liberated human subject has been rejuvenated in a time when corporate and business interests have proliferated, and arguably poisoned, the integrity of the pursuit of knowledge.

Humanism had become entrenched in European consciousness by the time Augustus Comte was writing about scientific progress in The Nature and Importance of the Positive Philosophy. Comte believes that a historical overview is necessary, “for no idea can be properly understood apart from its history” (45). He then seeks to systematise the development of thought by stating “that each branch of our knowledge, passes in succession through three theoretical states: the theological or fictitious state, the metaphysical or abstract state, and the scientific or positive state”. As a consequence, three methods for the pursuit of knowledge come to the fore: the theological method, which situates all phenomena as originating with divine influence; the metaphysical method, in which “the supernatural agents are replaced by abstract forces, real entities or personified abstractions” which are themselves in turn the originators of all phenomena; and the positive method, which recognizes “the impossibility of of obtaining absolute truth” and therefore “endeavours ... to discover, by a well-combined use of reasoning and observation, the actual laws of phenomena – that is to say, their invariable relations of succession and likeness”. Comte demonstrates an interesting self-awareness when he describes “the need at every epoch of having some theory to connect the facts” (46). His thinking is an extension of Bacon’s idea that the knowledge of reality must in principle come from observed phenomena. Thus, “it is no less true that, in order to observe, our mind has need of some theory or other”. However, in order to objectively navigate the near-infinite number of subjective understandings, observation of phenomena must be methodologically rigorous in order to properly understand both the self and the ‘truth’ that results from intellectual activity, for “it is experience alone which has enabled us to estimate our abilities rightly” (47).

It is to this end that he outlines the necessity of the positive philosophy, whose “fundamental character ... is to consider all phenomena as subject to invariable natural laws. The exact discovery of these laws and their reduction to the least possible number constitute the goal of all our efforts; for we regard the search after what are called causes, whether first or final, as absolutely inaccessible and unmeaning” (48). In this capacity, he rejects the metaphysical and theological arguments around the interpretation and realisation of divine will. In reductionist terms, everything necessary for the understanding of a given phenomenon is present within the phenomenon itself. The remainder of the chapter sketches “what stage in the formation of that philosophy has now been reached and what remains to be done in order to constitute it fully” (49). He argues that the pursuit of knowledge was rendered contingent with positivism first among the most simple and general of disciplines, as “astronomical phenomena ... were the first to be subjected to positive theories”, followed by a succession of physical sciences increasingly proximal to the human subject. This process originated with Aristotelian thinking and has taken place “continuously and at an increasing rate”. Comte recognizes that positive theories have not been adapted to the study of all phenomena, and there remains a great deal of research to be accomplished and a “gap” which must be bridged, as positive theories must be utilized in order to understand the dynamics of “social physics” (50).

The important dynamic inherent to Comte’s thinking is the reduction of different systems of thought to the same process of knowledge production, for when “our fundamental conceptions [have] thus been rendered homogeneous, philosophy will be consituted finally in the positive state,” at which point all theological and metaphysical methodologies and systems of thought will be rendered obsolete.The individual disciplines of scientific inquiry become established when they have “developed far enough to admit of separate cultivation – that is to say, when it has arrived at a stage in which it is capable of constituting the sole pursuit of certain minds” (51). Indeed, positivism has developed rather continuously since Bacon, to the point where Comte wishes to prove that “direct contemplation of the mind by itself is a pure illusion” (53), as the functioning of the brain is only observable from an objective position. Of course, Comte was not to live to see the developments in medical imaging technologies, which have indeed allowed the discipline of neuroscience to investigate the machinations of the brain in self-aware subjects. More provocatively, however, it is possible to interpret Comte’s statement that “interior observation gives rise to almost as many divergent opinions as there are so-called observers” (53) as prognosticating the development of psychoanalysis (which is of course one of the missing positive “social sciences”).

While Comte sates that the ancients were able to participate with significant contributions in numerous areas of scientific thought, due to the relatively immature state of their development, “it is ... impossible not to be struck by the great inconveniences which [the division into disciplines] produces.” He argues for the creation of an executive body given the task of providing an overview of the processes of each scientific discipline “to determine exactly the character of each science, to discover the relations and concatenation of the sciences, and to reduce, if possible, all their chief principles to the smallest number of common principles” (52). Scientists should be trained to have a general understanding of science before specializing. Furthermore, Comte calls for the creation of “a specific class on men, whose special and permanent function would consist in connecting each new special discovery with the general system”. To explain such a function, he emphasizes that understanding is essentially a singular discipline, and that the divisions of understanding into disciplines is an artificial principle which “by separating the difficulties, resolve[s] them more easily” (55). However, these distinctions can serve problematic when “questions arise which need to be treated by combining the points of view of several sciences”.

Comte states that positivism is the only ideological system which can be seen to be in ascent; the others have been in decline for centuries. This process will be completed once positivism has included the study of social phenomena, and furthermore that it is understood as a single and coherent theory which encompasses all of the disciplines of thought. When such has been accomplished, “the revolutionary crisis which harasses civilised people will then be at an end” (57). He concludes this section by stating that the endeavour to synthesize the various disciplines of human inquiry is not to reduce their variables to “one sole law”.  Fundamentally, the human mind is not able to realize perfection, which would be required for a valid and objective “sole law” for the understanding of all phenomena: “the resources of the human mind are too feeble, and the universe is too complicated, to admit of our ever attaining such scientific perfection”. In this context, it is interesting to note that Comte hints at the ‘holy grail’ of physics after Einstein, namely the unified field theory which seeks to harmonize theories of the macro universe (astronomy) with those concerned with the subatomic universe: “it seems to me that we could hope to arrive at it only by connecting all natural phenomena with the most general positive law with which we are acquainted – the law of gravitation – which already links all astronomical phenomena to some of the phenomena of terrestrial physics” (58). While dismissed by scholars and scientists of most disciplines, the quest for such unity remains at the heart of theoretical physics.


Notes

1.  A few decades after the Bacon’s death, the French monarch Louis XIV deployed the coincidental                existence of the human subject and the state as the philosophical – and indeed procedural – basis for his        reign.

2.  It can as a consequence be deduced that this line of reasoning will result in Heisenberg’s uncertainty              principle one hundred years later.

Thursday, August 05, 2010

The Hamilton Tiger-Cats are running scared




I am a regular supporter of the TiCats, and dreamed of playing on the team through my football-playing youth. I plan on attending this Saturday's game, and look forward to a Cats victory.

However, I am deeply saddened by the manner in which the TiCats organization is bullying the city over the new stadium. I have lived for most of my life in this city, and have worked diligently in the arts and education communities to help the city to succeed. The East Mountain stadium is a step in the wrong direction, for numerous reasons having to do with the quality of life in the city, the continuation of the revitalisation of businesses downtown, and the need for our social infrastructure and development plans to move away from the 'sprawl' mentality which is completely unsustainable.

I noticed that a 'rally' is being held today at Carmen's banquet centre (who would be the only beneficiaries from East Mountain outside of the TiCats). However, it seems that this is a limited seating event which required an RSVP. Such does not a rally make, but rather an instance of people agreeing with each other without having to face opponents. The East Mountain plan was pushed through at the last minute to sideswipe City Council and avoid debating the severe shortcomings of the proposal relative to the City's interests. Furthermore, the TiCats have not provided empirical figures demonstrating that West Harbour will fail. Consequently, the only conclusion a reasonable person can reach is that the TiCats are scared of allowing the benefits of East Mountain to speak for themselves. Instead, they use bully tactics to get their way in the face of concerted grassroots opposition. Their way IS the highway in this instance.

Personally, I feel that the Stadium would be best located near Confederation Park. Given the options of East Mountain or West Harbour, the residents and city of Hamilton will only benefit from West Harbour. The reason that the TiCats want East Mountain is so that they can monopolize the incidental profits from games -- parking, concessions, merchandise, etc. Public money will be spent on the stadium, and it should not be used to support private industry in this manner. Public money needs to be spent in the interests of the public. The public is interested in West Harbour.

Our City Our Future