Wednesday, February 19, 2014

Media and Materiality -- comprehensive examination -- 24-hour essay #1

MEDIA AND MATERIALITY
Question answered: #2. The content of communications media are often described and analysed as ‘texts’. Does this characterisation, unlike theories of the ontology of media proposed by Friedrich Kittler and Harold Innis, adequately describe media artifacts or are other models more appropriate to the investigation of media in general or with respect to specific media?

As communications media proliferate and emerge under new forms and configurations, it becomes increasingly difficult to maintain the content of such communication as coherent and autonomous objects of study.  While it is relatively clear that a book, a play, or a speech can be conceptualised as a singular entity which can be understood as ‘text’, the discreet, objective coherence of electronic media such as radio, television, and videogames strain and even breach traditional conceptions of media texts as objects of study. Fundamentally, such debates involve the extent to which ‘texts’ include the means of their recording – the trace of their physical existence – as well as the social relations which enable or disable reception of ‘texts’, within the framework of meaning produced in the communicative process. Can ‘texts’ be rationalised as unique, autonomous entities which generate meaning, or, as Kitler (2012) and Innis (1951) suggest, is meaning produced by a system of relations between individuals, institutions, and processes of communication? In order to begin such an inquiry, it is perhaps best to understand the origins of ‘text’ within the tradition of literary studies, from which the term derives.
The text emerged as an object of study in the nineteenth century with the proliferation of literature departments in universities in Europe and North America. Importantly, with the emergence of the text comes the emergence of the reader. In Orality and Literacy (1982), Walter Ong argues that as writing emerged out of oral cultural traditions, cognitive processes altered their sense of orientation from gestures of exteriority to gestures of interiority. This distinction between interior and exterior serves to initiate the constitution of literate individual subjects – what came to be understood as the Cartesian subject, the “I” at the centre of cogito ergo sum – as differentiated from pre-literate individuals who lacked subjectivity, who weren’t subjects. For Ong, individuals within oral cultures seek understanding within consensus, and ritualistic communicative practices form the basis for memory (22-23; 34). In this context, expertise (of interpretation, etc.) derives from the skill of an individual to manipulate and determine the group dynamic (35). Accordingly, meaning which derives from any particular communication process is an aggregation which accumulates (and, to later historical research, indexes) the expertise of a society into a unified communicative entity. Social power derives from a performative expression of the history of such aggregations (“I am king because I derive from these kings before me...”). Memory, as performance, is thus inherently non-historical and non-reflexive. Writing, on the other hand, fixes memory into a material process. Messages therefore are given a history and an individuality as objects, which thus allows individual readers to compare similar or divergent ideas. Literate societies promote the generation of multiple points of meaning centered upon the expertise of the individual making the claim to criticism. This process ultimately “free[s] the mind for more original, more abstract thought” (24).
It is thus possible to locate textuality, for Ong, within this same distinction: in oral societies, the ‘text’ is precisely the consensus of the group centred upon a given communicative process or message, enforced through ritual and a hierarchy of social power, in accord with a real-time experience of the world (1982 42-46); in literate societies, the ‘text’ is both a material and a discursive object which is to be reflected upon and interpreted by an individual subject (the reader). It is perhaps best to illustrate this notion of textuality with reference to religion. In the oral tradition, the consensus between priests and the community which elevated an individual to priesthood allows the successful continuation of a message (religious tradition) over time, despite the variabilities inherent to oral communicative processes, described by Ong as “dynamic” (32) and informed by interactions with an audience (65; 141). With literacy, however, individual reading subjects are able to interpret a given message with reference to their own experience and expertise, as well as to other written materials produced by other reflective individual subjects. It is this theoretical objectivity of the written word which enables and informs the autonomy of the text, offered as an object of study. This process accelerated with the development of print technologies, which, in addition to multiplying the scale and extent of available literary works, “embedded the word in space more definitively” and initiated new forms of written works such as indexes and lists (120-1) as well as the “quantification of knowledge” (127). Furthermore, by objectifying communication as written word, print encouraged the conception of privacy, both in terms of the private individual reading to him- or herself, and also in terms of the commercial operations in which such literacy functioned (128).
In this context, it is possible to understand the conception of ‘text’ as produced by literary studies: a discreet and autonomous object distributed as an object to a reading public and which, by means of an Althusserian interpellative gesture which creates the reader (in other words, the message recipient) as subject able to privately judge both the value of the object (text) itself as well as engage in a public discursive process of critical inquiry and comparison. The text is itself therefore a historical subject, both influencing and being influenced by the processes by which it is interpreted and given meaning. The index of these changes in processes of interpretation can be understood to constitute the field of study in which the object is discussed (Literature, Music, Cinema, etc.). We can therefore presently conclude this line of reasoning with the following generalisations, which the remainder of this essay will complicate: a text is a communicative practice-made-object which constitutes the reading subject which interprets it; a text is a body of words seeking interpretation by a reader; a text has meaning. On one end of a continuum of sorts lies the text; on the other is located the reading subject.
However, there are several problems, or indeed contradictions, even, with this conception of textuality. The principal issue involves the separation of the text as discreet from the reading subject or the context in which the text is experienced. As Marshall McLuhan argues in Understanding Media (1994), the meaning of a message cannot be separated from the context in which the message is sent and received. This conception of meaning (and, by extension, textuality) is informed by the transformations to communication processes inaugurated by their electrification. McLuhan argues that the electrification of communication alters the temporality of both message and receiving subject, and by this alteration fundamentally transforms both the message and its audience (12) by “overthrow[ing] the privileged position of the “contents” of the media, substituting a new sign language of rhetorical and symbolic effects” (Kroker 54). Electricity changes the speed of access to information, with spatial and temporal consequences to the positions taken by sender, message (‘text’), and recipient, a transformation conceptualised by McLuhan as an implosion between texts and individuals. In this capacity, McLuhan’s ideation of media as the extensions of human nervous system (sense and cognitive organs) can be understood to undermine the conception of textuality as defined by the literary studies from which he as a scholar emerged. If writing exteriorises and instrumentalises memory and print extends the reach of such memories in both space and time by means of mechanical reproducibility, electrical communications interiorises the infrastructure by which text and reading subject are brought into an instantaneous whole. McLuhan here identifies two instantiations: ‘hot’ media, in which participation of experiencing subject with the text is minimal, and ‘cool’ media, in which a more engaged participation of the experiencing subject is demanded (1994 23). In this capacity, any sense of meaning as derived from a communication process must account not only for what literary studies understands as constituting the text, but also for the means by which the interpreting subject experiences the text. As the meaning of an electrified communication process is altered by the instantaneity of its reception, it is therefore possible to understand textuality for McLuhan as precisely the implosive circuit by which text and reading subject are made instantaneous and co-terminal.
Gary Genosko (1999) identifies within McLuhan’s work a Platonic ideation of speech as the medium most capable of the pure expression of the will of the individual, which “place[s] McLuhan firmly in the Western metaphysical tradition” (41). For McLuhan, speech (oral culture) functions as a transcendental signifier contained at the heart of all media (Jhally 167). As all subsequent media involve within their ontology the individuals who experience them as dependent on the technologies which enable this experience, the textual artifacts of mediated communication processes (i.e., messages) are ideologically determined by the technologies which enable them as media. Consequently, the autonomy of the individual interpreting subject (i.e., the reader) is called into question alongside the autonomy of the text. As McLuhan illustrates by means of his discussion of electric light – the only medium in which there is no ‘content’ (1994 8-9) – all media contain within them the other forms of media which they supplement and replace. As such, within McLuhan’s terms it is possible therefore to conceptualise the ‘text’ within any given process of communication not as a singular object of study, but rather as a constellation or circuit of media artifacts tracing their origination in speech as informed by the configuration of technologies which enable and constitute them as representational media.
McLuhan derived his theories from the work of Harold Innis. For Innis, any concession to textuality must be tempered by his understanding of communications as occurring within a social matrix of institutions – abstracted entities such as religion and the law, which are obviously grounded in their material function within society – and communicative processes between institutions and individuals. Meaning, as such, is itself governed by the particular configuration of communicative patterns. Like McLuhan, Innis conceives of texts as being relational entities which are informative (and transformative) on social structures as a whole. As Sut Jhally (1993) notes, “[f]or Innis, the most critical factor in society is the way in which means of communication provide a framework of possibilities and parameters ... within which social power (as well as modes of cognition) operate” (165). Texts can be broadly defined as artifacts produced from monopolies of knowledge. However, according to Innis the web of social relations which produce such monopolies of knowledge are informed by the material conditions under which the possibilities for communication are structured. In Empire and Communications (2007), Innis traces the development of cultural production from the oral tradition to the development of electronic broadcast media. He argues that media organize power along two continua: time and space. In order to extend through time, media need to exist in a materially-durable form, which, as a consequence, limits transportation and thus curtails the extension of the message (and the power contingent with its expression) in space (1951 33). Alternately, media which are easily transported and thus allow for a wide spatial dispersion do not enjoy a material existence which favours temporal durability. It is this bias within processes of communication which confers social power to the agent who produces and/or receives it. If communication processes are understood as texts contingent with the literary tradition, then they could not possibly inform social relations as Innis suggests, as meaning produced by a text would precipitate from social relations and not vice versa. However, as Innis’s illustration of the influence of writing on the development of the Roman empire in Empire and Communications suggests, communication processes are as informative of the society which produced them as they are in turn informed by that society. In effect, the production of meaning is complicated by the incorporation of the network of social relations in which the text is produced, received, and evaluated into what literary studies would regard as the ‘text’. Ultimately, therefore, it is not possible to locate textuality within Innis’s theoretical framework; texts do not self-regulate meaning by some internal cohesion, but instead exist as relational nodes within what William Kuhns describes as an “ecology of information” (as quoted in Jhally, 165).
In this sense, McLuhan’s and Innis’s arguments about media are as grounded in material existence as are the historical materialists who followed in the wake of Marx. However, as Genosko notes, McLuhan’s work can be faulted for ignoring the political economy of both communication practice and the discursive communities in which communication takes place (1999 29). For Raymond Williams (1958), a “Marxist theory of culture  ... will take the facts of the economic structure and the consequent social relations as the guiding string on which a culture is woven” (269). A ‘leap of faith’, in a sense, is then required in order to bridge the ontological gap between materiality and cognition. Namely, there are competing, but not necessarily exclusive, theories concerning the grounds by which a given ideology or cognitive process could emerge from material conditions to affect a subject, constituted in terms of either (both) the individual who thinks as well as the social body in which a multitude of individuals communicate and operate by means of a common ideological currency. Theodor Adorno (1991) argues that cultural artifacts produced for and under the influence of the commercial market are debased and rendered banal by their transformation into commodities, while simultaneously noting that the negative effects of what he terms the “culture industry” have not been empirically demonstrated (105). In this context, Grossberg (1984) indicates that the “politics of textuality signals the changing meaning and function of the category “text” ” (392). In “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction”, Walter Benjamin (1968) argues that the mechanical reproduction of an artwork has a more significant “wither[ing]” (221) effect on it than does its commercialization, although the two may indeed be highly related. For Benjamin, the mechanical duplication of an artwork “substitutes a plurality of copies for a unique existence”, thus eliminating the “presence of the original [as] the prerequisite to the concept of authenticity” (220).
In such theoretical figurations, not only are texts understood within the material conditions of their existence, but so too are interpreting subjects. As Jürgen Habermas argues in The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (1989), the seeming cognitive freedom of the individual reading subject is bound up in the constitution of that subject within a discursive public sphere founded in a tradition of aristocratic and bourgeois privilege. Habermas argues that the culture which developed (around) writing was a process in which private individuals, using the material resources granted them through ownership of capital accumulated through finance and trade capitalism (14-15), are able to engage in debate and exchange of information within a newly-constituted bourgeois public sphere. Habermas argues that it was this change, rather than print per se, which allowed for the development of an autonomous individual subject, able to judge and act upon their interpretation of the world of communication in which they were equal members (18). Accordingly, those communications practices which were elevated to the status of ‘text’ were precisely those written works which reflected the interests and social authority of those “private people come together as a public” in order to study them (27).
One may infer in Habermas’s thought that since private individuals tend to erase or be ignorant of the marks of their privilege, as do the institutions which serve to perpetuate these privileges, textuality incorporates the processes of social censure which include certain communication practices as ‘texts’ while excluding others as unworthy of study. This social censure constitutes the political economy of textuality. Habermas’s examination of music in this context is particularly informative. When the notion of the public was grounded upon aristocratic privilege and function, music was defined (as text) by the importance of the occasion of its presentation; music was written for specific courtly functions and events, and conferred to the listening subject the meaning of the event for which the music was composed. However, by the eighteenth century music had been “[r]eleased from its functions in the service of social representation [and] became an object of free choice and of changing preference” (39-40). The bourgeois public sphere authorised not only any given communication process as an autonomous text, but also the recipient of communication as a human individual able to discuss the meaning that was interpreted in those textual objects determined to be worthy of study. Meaning generated by textuality was therefore dependent on “mutual relationships between privatized individuals who were psychologically interested in what was “human” in self-knowledge” (50). Of course, Habermas is quick to note that such self-knowledge does not include knowledges exterior to the bourgeois public sphere; in other words, such knowledge of the self was limited to the ‘selves’ gifted with male, European, bourgeois privilege (or the derivation of this privilege in North America), and not their servants (which may, by extension, include the totality of individuals who are not economically enfranchised), spouses, or children (56). To return to literary and cultural studies for a brief moment, it is thus possible to understand the accommodation of the voices and literatures of such marginalised ‘selves’ as the identity politics which characterise the contemporary condition of those academic disciplines which have as their object of study a ‘text’, in one capacity or another (postcolonial and feminist reclamations of ‘forgotten’, ‘lost’, or marginal literary works within the framework of Literature, for example).
Also emerging from the Marxist critical tradition, the work of Pierre Bourdieu further problematises the notion that a text is an autonomous entity. In The Field of Cultural Production (1994), Bourdieu argues that “works of art exist as symbolic objects only if they are ... socially instituted as works of art and received by spectators capable of knowing and recognizing them as such” (37). In other words, texts are communication structures which are fixed in place by means of a field of social and institutional relations, themselves consisting of a variety of socio-economic hierarchies (40-43), in which they are produced and received and which ultimately inform the text as an object for consumption within a marketplace. The relation of these hierarchies Bourdieu identifies with the term dispositions, which conjoins a subject’s performance of a social role with the degree of status conferred on the subject by that role (63). While these dispositions are informed by the material conditions under which the individual operates, their interiorization into consciousness is the ground upon which subjectivity (the will of the individual) and objectivity (the determination of consciousness by the structures in which an individual operates) resolve into a unified entity. Relations between individuals come to form a system which Bourdieu names habitus (1984 6), and which comes to describe the manner in which meaning (and thus textuality) is reproduced within society. Bourdieu thus reads a political economy into each instance of communication and reception in which education and social class come to inform cultural practices (1994 13). By means of a mapped (and quantified) matrix of relations, it is possible to quantify and predict patterns of cultural production and reception. In this manner, Bourdieu’s work can be understood to determine textuality as existing within a field of relationships. In other words, texts cannot be defined as objects which produce or contain meaning autonomous from their reception. Texts are not discreet entities, but rather are produced in conjunction with the individuals which receive them. Extrapolating from Bourdieu’s work, it is possible to locate ‘texts’ as instantiations of social relations which are informed by the structures of their dissemination and reception. Much like McLuhan and Innis, then, Bourdieu incorporates and involves the network of reception and production into the positions taken by both text and individual experiencing the text.   
In opposition to McLuhan’s belief in media as the extension of the human body, with the consequent ideation of the various media serving to augment the multitude of human sense organs, in Gramophone, Film, Typewriter (1999) Friedrich Kitler proposes a kind of technological determinism for mediated expression in which all forms of media (and their contingent technologies) develop along a continuum of inscription. Contemporary electronic media incorporate the time of their inscription into themselves “as a mixture of audio frequencies in the acoustic realm and as the movement of single-image sequences in the optical” (3). Kittler’s position further undermines the literary conception of the ‘text’, as well as the individual human subject who ‘reads’ it. For Kittler, the individual human recipient of communication process “escapes into apparatuses” as “the technological differentiation of optics, acoustics, and writing exploded Gutenberg’s writing monopoly” (16). And yet Kittler is dubious that the liberation of technological recording capacities serves to liberate the human subject; indeed, humans are incorporated along with ‘texts’ into a continuum of inscription. Once media incorporate perceptual (i.e., optical and auditory) information as the inscribed content of communication processes, those media functionally include the procedural and perceptual elements of their interaction along with ‘reading’ subjects into the inscription (‘text’) itself. Kittler illustrates this idea with reference to the recording of music. The ‘text’ of a live musical performance is the performance itself; this performance may also refer to a printed musical text upon which the performance was structured. However, when manipulating a tape recording of a musical performance, “what is manipulated is the real rather than the symbolic” (35). In other words, this communication process incorporates the ‘reality’ of an individual experiencing the temporal process of the inscription of sound as itself a referent for the constitution of that reality; meaning derived from the manipulated recorded sound has more to do with the temporality of the original being altered in toto by the manipulation, rather than solely by the sounds generated as a result of this manipulation.[i]  
This process of inscription of optical and auditory information, of course, causes any notion of textual meaning to be dependent on technological processes. Kittler further complicates the conception of media as ‘texts’ by implicating the scriptural traces of Norbert Wiener’s (1967) notion of cybernetic control, with particular reference to the processes of feedback inherent to cybernetic systems (Kittler 110). In the cybernetic framework provided by Wiener, it is possible to understand the relation of the commercial marketplace to both inscription (text) and audience as mutually informative. Ultimately, for Kittler the social transformations contingent with electronic media render “indistinguishable what is human and what is machine” (146), as ‘text’ and process of interpretation fold into each other. It is consequently difficult to conclude that notions of textuality are sufficient to accommodate Kittler’s concerns.
The examination of textuality here embarked upon challenges the notion that the content of communication media can be legitimately characterised as a ‘text’.  Originating in literary studies as a singular and coherent object of study, the proliferation of electric media demonstrates the continued use of this concept to be increasingly strained, as the content of communications processes includes the network or circuit connecting the message, producer, and recipient.




[i] Although it is outside the scope of this present essay, I would like to note that in this context can be understood the ontology of musique concrète and sampling as structural forms and musical elements. 




BIBLIOGRAPHY


Adorno, Theodor. “Culture Industry Reconsidered.” The Culture Industry. New York: Routledge, 1991. 98-106.

Althusser, Louis. “Ideological State Apparatuses (Note Towards an Investigation).” Lenin and Philosophy and Other
     Essays
. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971. 127-186.

Benjamin, Walter. “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction” Illuminations. New York: Shocken
     Books, 1968. 217-252.

Bourdieu, Pierre. The Field of Cultural Production. New York: Columbia UP, 1993. 29-141, 215-237.
---            Distinction. Cambridge, USA: Harvard UP, 1984. 97-256, 372-484.

Genosko, Gary. McLuhan and Baudrillard: the masters of implosion. New York: Routledge, 1999.

Grossberg, Lawrence. “Strategies of Marxist cultural interpretation.” Critical Studies in Media Communication 1.4
     (1984): 392-421.

Habermas, Jurgen. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere. Trans. Thomas Burger. Cambridge, USA: MIT
     Press, 1989. 1-56.

Innis, Harold. Empire and Communications. Toronto: Dundurn Press, 2007.
---            The Bias of Communication. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1951.

Jhally, S. “Communications and the Materialist Conception of History: Marx, Innis and Technology.” Continuum 7.1
     (1993): 161-182.

Kittler, Friedrich.  Gramophone, Film, Typewriter. Stanford, USA: Stanford UP, 1999.

Kroker, Arthur. Technology and the Canadian Mind. Montreal: New World Perspectives. 1984.

McLuhan, Marshall. Understanding Media: the Extensions of Man. Cambridge, USA: The MIT Press, 1994.

Ong, Walter. Orality and Literacy. New York: Routledge, 1982.

Wiener, Norbert. The Human Use of Human Beings: Cybernetics and Society. London: Free Association Books, 1967.

Williams, Raymond. Culture and Society 1780-1950. New York: Harper & Row, 1958.

No comments: