CINEMA, TELEVISION,
AND NEW MEDIA
Question answered: #2. Are the essential distinctions (if they indeed exist) between media eroded by recent transformations in production and exhibition practice, and do specific media respond to these transformations in particular ways?
Question answered: #2. Are the essential distinctions (if they indeed exist) between media eroded by recent transformations in production and exhibition practice, and do specific media respond to these transformations in particular ways?
The twenty-first century has witnessed profound developments in the production and consumption of media. As Marshall McLuhan (1994), Harold Innis (1951), and Friedrich Kittler (1999) argue, the most profound transformation has been the introduction and development of electrical technologies to communications practices. With electricity came the possibility to reproduce perceptual experiences in order to enable such experiences as new media, distinct from the media associated with the reproduction of speech in written language. The most obvious examples in this regard involve the recording and distribution of sound and motion images. The development of technologies related to these perceptual activities quickly crystallized into media relative to fundamental technological differences; for example, radio and consumer recording formats distributed recorded sound (music, conversation, audio dramas), while film and television distributed recorded motion images along with accompanying sound (films, television shows). A further technological distinction centred upon speed and ease of accessibility can be made between distribution systems and consumption practices relative to such recordings. While this paper will illustrate a few arguments in favour of such essentialist determinations for the differences between media, ultimately a more flexible understanding of the ontology of media will be presented. Indeed, as this paper will demonstrate, it is computer technologies – and specifically home computer technologies – which signal the true transformation in media (and, by extension, mediation), largely due to the new forms of media which have emerged along with the technology.
Cinema demonstrates how definitions of media can be grounded in both
essentialist and non-essentialist claims. Critical activity has focused on the
manner in which the materiality of film production and reception practices defines
the medium. Jean-Louis Baudry, for example, outlines an “apparatus” in which
the production and reception of film takes place: the photographic process of
inscription onto film by means of lenses and photochemistry, the optical
projection of film onto a white screen, the spectator in the cinema (1986 288).
For Baudry, grounded as he is in historical materialism, such an apparatus is
an ideological one at each stage of production and reception. Consequently, any
change in the orientation or constitution of this apparatus will alter the
ideological effects which can be determined as a result. Christian Metz (1982)
argues that the technological configuration of cinema is analogous to the
processes of the human unconscious. Metz’s connection of psychoanalysis to a
technological apparatus condemns his theory to obsolescence as the technologies
which form that apparatus develop and new ones are introduced while old ones
are subtracted (Manovich 294), as well as by developments in psychoanalytic
theory which may subvert or emphasise the Freudian theoretical apparatus
foundational to Metz’s work. The work of other scholars such as Laura Mulvey
(1975) and Žižek (2004), who have deployed psychoanalytic readings to define
cinema in less essentialist terms, has proven more adaptive to technological
change. By means of a reading of Bergson’s conception of durée, and a reflexive negation of psychoanalytic theory (fully
expressed in Anti-Oedipus), Deleuze
(1989) argues that the gap between static images which enables the illusion of motion
for cinema to occur temporalises the spectator, interpellating them into
subjectivity by means of an affective involvement with the image (47), and
anticipates montage, itself commonly understood (Metz 1985; Bordwell 1986;
Elsaesser 2012) to be the grammar of cinema. Scholars such as Schatz (1989) and
Elsaesser have extended the definition of this apparatus to include the
hegemonic forces at play within the market. Both scholars define Hollywood as the
articulation of a material and symbolic hegemony positioned to institutionalise
and standardise its narrative forms, production processes, and distribution and
consumption practices. Elsaesser argues that by means of their dominant
position in the production and consumption of film, Hollywood can be seen to
determine and define the medium of film as a whole into an experience between particular
types of films and particular types of spectators, going so far as to state
that the function of narrative in Hollywood films “lay in the resources and
organizational assets which could be accumulated around it” (2012 152) and
order audiences accordingly. These institutionalised forms actively displace
certain forms and definitions for the medium while enabling others. As Bordwell,
Doane (1989), and Adorno (1991) argue, film has come to be defined as a medium
primarily by the market forces which affect its production, distribution, and
consumption. Indeed, the same forces which integrate media companies into
multinational conglomerates force the various media created and distributed by
the newly integrated subsidiaries to interact, cross-pollinate, and subsume
each other (Mattelart 2000). Indeed, Grossberg (1992) argues that popular
culture, as the result of such processes of media hegemony, is a significant
agent in the dilution of the boundaries between media.
Viewed as a whole, then, many of these definitions for cinema do not
maintain their coherence in the wake of new technologies for the production and
reception of film. One wonders, for example, how Deleuze’s elevation of the ‘ontological’
gap at the heart of the cinematic process if cameras recorded at much higher
speeds than the twenty-four frames per second adopted as the standard for
cinema by the 1920s. If Hollywood can be seen to adapt and incorporate elements
of the avant garde and international and marginalised cinemas — which may themselves
be empowered by being influenced by Hollywood – then what does it mean to
define a medium around the dominant forces within it? In a similar
manner, notions of spectatorship dependent on the public exhibition of films have
been challenged by the private consumption of cinema by means of television and
home video.
Indeed, as a medium for the reception of broadcasting as well as the
device enabling other media such as home video and videogames, television
considerably problematises essentialist boundaries between media. Arguing in Television:
Technology and Cultural Form (1990) that the serial and segmented nature of
television programming is shaped to a considerable extent by television’s
existence as a commercial entity, Raymond Williams identifies the concept of
“flow” to define the medium (86). It is precisely this ephemeral and amorphous
conception of television which has allowed the medium to adapt to technological
change and the development of competing media such as film and the internet. Television,
according to Williams, has the “technological capacity to absorb and circulate
every kind of cultural energy” (Dienst 13). Furthermore, broadcast media such
as television and radio, unlike other media, exist within what may be described
as the perpetual present of their exhibition. While there is no technological
reason for any broadcast medium to broadcast perpetually (twenty-four hours per
day), an extension of Innis’s (1951) notion of the space bias of ephemeral
media such as radio and television may explain the reasons behind this
perpetual present, as the ease by which broadcast signals are ‘transported’
into the homes of consumers, as well as the fact that such media are consumed
for ‘free’ in exchange for advertising (Browne 175), destines broadcast media
to an existence of continuity. Furthermore, while film, ostensibly the closest
analogue to television, can be understood as having incorporated aspects of
theatrical and musical performance, painting, photography, dance, and
literature, Williams argues that television can be understood as having further
incorporated aspects of radio, journalism, advertising, and live spectatorship
(1990 44ff). Television incorporates the many discreet aspects of itself –
advertisements, announcements, news, “introductory and interstitial materials”
– into what Nick Browne (1984) describes as a “supertext” whose essence is “one
of flow, banality, distraction, and transience” (176), as spectators order
their own viewing experience among a multiplicity of constitutive elements.
It is this multiplicity of function and form which differentiates broadcast
media from non-broadcast media. According to Williams, unlike a book, a play, a
song, or even a film, which constitute discreet objects and experiences, in broadcast
media “the real programme that is offered is a sequence or set of alternative sequences” (1990 87). It should not then
be surprising that as new technologies related to the distribution of
television have developed, the notion of flow as foundational to television has
been challenged. William Uricchio (2004) argues that “the present day’s
convergent technologies, economies, and textual networks have ... subverted ...
the logics of television [and] have also transformed the medium’s content and
cultural place” (165). If, as Lynn Spigel suggests in Make Room for TV (1992), the introduction of television served to
order spaces within the household and define television spectatorship along
lines contingent with the consumption of consumer products, then it is possible
to extend this interpretation to contemporary changes in forms and patterns of
television spectatorship as contingent with changes to the home inaugurated by
home computer technologies which are in the process of subsuming television
into the internet. Disrupted first by technologies of home video recording and
storage, the capacity for broadcasting to order the reception practices of
spectators has been undermined by the digital distribution of television. Home
video, on-demand and time-shifted video services, and internet streaming (as
well as ‘illegal’ downloading) of television programming has further altered
spectator relations to the television “supertext”. A recent example of a
television show broadcast under two different configurations of television
serves to illustrate this point. The British show House of Cards, broadcast as a mini-series in 1990, used a
‘cliff-hanger’ ending centred upon the murder of a prominent character by the
show’s protagonist. The narrative significance of dramatic events such as this often
provoked their deployment as ‘cliff-hangers’ at the end of television shows or
seasons to provoke viewer anticipation of the next episode and encourage them
to schedule future instances of viewership.[i]
For the 2013 American remake, distributed (‘broadcast’) as an entire season
without delay between episodes on the digital streaming subscription service
Netflix, a similarly dramatic killing by the show’s protagonist is located in
the middle of the first episode of the season, indicating that the event is
structured in a manner suggesting the ‘binge watching’ habits typical of
Netflix (and, by extension, digital streaming and home video) viewers.
Spigel argues that television served to “reassemble the splintered lives
of families [and] .... reinforce the new suburban family unit” (1992 39)
centred upon the new postwar consumer society. Ultimately, such changes were
inaugurated by technologies of mobility and communication which extended
ideations of inclusion and privacy from the home to a virtual space bounded by
the reach of transportation and communications technology, which in turn orders
the real space in which patterns of mobility and communication occur. Williams subsumes
the social relations inaugurated by such technologies and living conditions under
the concept of mobile privatisation, the
social product of which is “[b]roadcasting in its applied form” (1990 20). Spigel
thus traces the incorporation of the machine elements of industrial activity
(dishwashers, sewing machines, etc.) into the home as contingent with “the
spatial condensation of work and viewing” (1992 89), while Anna McCarthy (2001)
outlines the incorporation of television into public spaces such as workplaces,
transportation hubs, and shopping centres. By means of the surveillance and
production of consumer activity, broadcast media such as television realise
what Mark Andrejevic (2002) names “consumer labor” (230). Jhally and Livant
(1986, quoted in Andrejevic) characterise the value exchange between viewers
who watch ‘free’ programs and advertisers who pay for television programming as
the “work of watching” (235). Such labor relations form the initial gesture of
spectatorial participation which, as outlined below, will come to define the
ontology of media.
As suggested by Spigel’s illustration of the extent to which daytime
programming was informed by the daily chores performed by the women who were
the primary audience, television was itself ordered by spectators as much as it
ordered their patterns of viewership and stimulated the consumption of consumer
goods. In other words, as television presented and ordered itself as a consumer
product, audiences responded by altering television to meet their needs as consumers.
As Matt Carlson (2006) illustrates, consumer products related to the
consumption of television have altered not only patterns of viewership, but
also the content of television programs. In this capacity, television can be
seen to order time as well as space. First, home video recording freed television
audiences from the broadcast schedule and, by means of the archival nature of
video cassettes, allowed television programming to be reified as an object of
secondary relation to television as a broadcast medium. The digitisation of
television broadcasting as well as the development of digital video recorders
capable of time-shifting and altering programming nearly in real-time has further
transformed viewer interactions with television from a process of scheduling
(viewers watching shows at specific times not under their control) to one of
surveillance. For Carlson, surveillance indicates the manner in which digital broadcast
technologies allow broadcasters to precisely monitor viewer activity and accordingly
alter the products offered for viewing (102-103). In this capacity, it is
possible to extend conceptions of ‘liveness’ related to the television “supertext”
to the real-time surveillance of the audience itself. Arguably, the surveillance
of digital television media merely extends to television producers the feedback
processes between audience and performer which informed not only live studio
television but also the live forms of performance (theatre, Vaudeville) which
provided the content for television in its earliest years (Williams 64-65).
In a somewhat abstract manner, it is possible to locate ‘liveness’ as
both reifying and enabling the structures of life described by mobile privatisation. In addition to
Williams, other critics have also focused upon television’s ‘liveness’ as a
distinguishing element of the medium. Jerome Bourdon (2000) argues that while
‘liveness’ was inherent to television before the advent of video storage
technologies, live broadcasting has since been institutionalised as a means of affirming
the hegemonic position of television broadcasters by providing a closure of
space and time between event and spectator (534) and as a means to confer a
degree of “‘authenticity’ and ‘truth’” (533) to the programs being broadcasted.
Indeed, ‘liveness’, which incorporates the viewer into media exhibition, can be
understood as the precursor to spectator participation. As Bourdon notes,
“liveness should be interpreted as a development within media history as a
whole” (551). He likens viewers switching to the news from other programs – multitasking
between shows and other media – as a new form of liveness (553). Indeed, ultimately
the ostensibly minimal amount of spectator participation demonstrated by
television viewers using their remote control to order the sequence of
television programming belongs on a continuum of interactivity and media
control which leads to computational technologies which demand ‘spectatorial’
participation. In this context, Richard Dienst (1994) notes that the apparatus
of television as constructed by Williams ignores “the possibility that the very
notions of transmission and reception ... belong to the apparatus itself” (16).
Accordingly, Williams’s conception of ‘flow’ in Television, whose publication predates the development of home
video and home computer technologies, does not account for the capacity for
audiences to construct and modify the programs they are watching. Notably, the capacity
for commercial television to structure the ideological responses of viewers is
undermined by the ability of viewers to ignore or remove advertising from shows
and structure patterns of viewing around their personal schedules due to home
recording and digital distribution, and ultimately use consumer digital video
technologies to produce their own televisual content and distribute it on the
internet. Indeed, the digitization of media undermines the ‘integrity of the
medium’ not only for television and for television studies, but also for all
media which undergo processes of digitization.
In Gramophone, Film, Typewriter
(1999), Friedrich Kittler notes that the digitization of optical, acoustic, and
writing media allows their “distinct data flows” to be reunited (170), and
concludes his examination by identifying the computer as the logical conflagration
of other media technologies and real-time computation, in the guise of “machine
subjects”, as the contemporary terminus of the development of technologies of
inscription (259). He rather boldly states his lack of respect for the
distinction between media, noting that the traditional differentiations of
media based on recording technology and human perceptual apparatus (seeing and
hearing, for example) are fundamentally undermined by electric communications
and recording technology. With the advent of digitisation, the variety of
information forms “are reduced to surface effects, known to consumers as
interface” (1). Indeed, it is by means of interface that consumers come to
understand and differentiate digital media. Under the aegis of digitization,
digital video, for example, is not an experience of ‘television’ or ‘cinema’;
rather, it is enabled by the interface which exhibits it. The use of computers
to consume audio, visual, and textual materials indicates that the
screen-as-interface is more informative to understanding a mediated process
than are traditional conceptions of media distinction grounded in differences
in perceptual or recording technology. Television programming is easily adapted
to distribution and ‘exhibition’ on the internet due to the fact that, in reductive
terms, high-resolution computer screens make great high-resolution digital
televisions.
More importantly than simply providing another platform for the
distribution and consumption of audio-visual material incorporated from other
media distribution apparatuses, home computer technologies signal the extent to
which spectator participation has been incorporated into systems of media
production and consumption. As Lev Manovich (2001) argues, the “meta-medium of
the digital computer” (6) instantiates new media not dependent on perceptual or
aesthetic characteristics but rather as “subject to algorithmic manipulation”
(27). The algorithmic nature of digital media has two effects, the first of
which serves to explain the transformational nature of digitisation. Manovich
argues that digital media are modular, variable, and iterative, and in this
capacity recent transformations in television broadcasting can be rationalised.
The second effect of digital media is more philosophical in nature. In addition
to signalling the increasing involvement of audiences into the ‘text’ of media
on account of developments in the technologies of broadcasting, the above
examination of television demonstrates McLuhan’s principle that all media
contain within them previous forms of media. Of course, the incorporation of
one medium within another is not a one-directional process of ‘new’ media
incorporating ‘old’ media, as demonstrated by the incorporation of photography
into newsprint. Rather, the response of cinema and television to the advent of
computing technologies illustrates that media often deploy whichever other
popular or useful media can be reasonably incorporated into them. From such a
position, it is possible to extrapolate from Rick Altman’s suggestion regarding
film that “[g]enres must be understood discursively” (1999 121) and conclude
that media themselves function similarly as discursive practices.
One vector of such a discursive practice is indicated by the notable
sense of determination present in McLuhan’s thought. The incorporation of media
into new forms enabled by the development of technology implies what Walter
Benjamin (1968) describes within history as the “weak Messianic power” (254) in
which the past involves the present. Indeed, it is thus possible to read
McLuhan’s belief that media subsume within them previous forms of media through
a Heideggerian lens, as such a process describes what for Heidegger was the
essence of all technology to gather into itself all forms of potential energies
as “standing-reserve” (1977 24). In such terms, the destining of all media is
toward a totalising sense perception and recording which reveals all possible
information to the user. In order to fully understand the implications of
computerisation on the media examined in this essay, we must turn to Dienst’s
rather Platonic suggestion that “all actually existing television systems are
in some sense a failed totalization of an ideal visuality” (1994 11). If the
contemporary configuration of television has incorporated (or is being
incorporated into) forms of digital content and distribution (i.e., the
internet), then it is possible to position television, as Meyrowitz (1995) does,
as a “widening of sensory experience” (40-41). Accordingly, contemporary forms
of television incorporate aspects of visuality and ‘liveness’ from other media:
news programming which, like the internet, structures textual information as
visual elements; social media (message boards, Facebook, Twitter) interaction
between viewers and show producers or fictional characters of dramatic programs,
such as The Hills and General Hospital; and webcasts and
podcasts which supplement or augment the broadcasting of shows. However, the
digitization of media has had a more profound transformative effect on media
than is represented by the increasing interaction between audiences and media
content. It is possible to further extend Dienst’s notion of “ideal visuality”
by means of Paul Virilio’s equation of processes and technologies of visibility
with calculation, as elaborated in War
and Cinema (1989) and The Information
Bomb (2000). Arguing that technologies of visibility emerged as tools for
war and the colonial organization of space, Virilio describes modes of
visibility aided by computation as active
optics (2000 14). Such optics exponentially increase the capacity for
individuals to generate and process information, with the consequence that individuals
will experience “a speed change in the order of time as it is lived” (1989 45),
and thus “leave intact neither the old aesthetics ... nor the ethics” which
came to define traditional media and the societies in which they circulate (2000
121).
As outlined above, the polyvalent nature of digital media, as algorithmic
processes, fulfils the Heideggerian ‘gathering’ of the possibilities for vision
into a singular technical apparatus enabling the successful realisation of
“ideal visuality”. Home computer technologies involve media in a computational
process which interpellates spectators as users. While videogames, software,
and the internet represent the most obvious insertion of interaction and
participation as an essential component defining the medium, these forms of
media are merely the most contemporary articulations of long-extant trends in
media. Consequently, it is difficult to determine contemporary communications
media with the essentialist formulations which often served to inaugurate the
critical apparatuses which arose in response to them.
[i] It
should be here noted that the ‘cliff-hanger’ serves a slightly modified purpose
for the British House of Cards. By
using such a narrative device at the end of a four-episode mini-series which
was not intended for development into a broadcast series, the cliff-hanger
ending serves (much like its use as a genre convention in horror films) to
confer a mark of reality to the show by invoking in viewers a projection of the
character from the temporality of the show ‘offscreen’ into the imagined
temporal space ‘after’ the show ends.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Adorno,
Theodor. “Culture Industry Reconsidered.” The
Culture Industry. New York: Routledge, 1991. 98-106.
Althusser,
Louis. “Ideological State Apparatuses (Note Towards an Investigation).” Lenin and Philosophy and Other
Essays. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971. 127-186.
Essays. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971. 127-186.
Altman,
Rick. Film/Genre. London: BFI
Publishing, 1999.
Andrejevic,
Mark. “The work of being watched: interactive media and the exploitation of
self-disclosure.” Critical Studies in
Media Communication 19.2 (2002): 230-248.
Baudry,
Jean-Louis. “Ideological Effects of the Basic Cinematic Apparatus”. Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology.
Ed. Philip Rosen. New York: Columbia UP, 1986. 286-298.
Ed. Philip Rosen. New York: Columbia UP, 1986. 286-298.
Benjamin, Walter. “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical
Reproduction” Illuminations. New York: Shocken
Books, 1968. 217-252.
Books, 1968. 217-252.
Bordwell, David. “Classical
Hollywood Cinema: Narrational Principles and Procedures.” Narrative, Apparatus,
Ideology. Ed. Philip Rosen. New York: Columbia UP, 1986. 17-34.
Ideology. Ed. Philip Rosen. New York: Columbia UP, 1986. 17-34.
Bourdon, Jerome. “Live television is still alive: on television as an
unfulfilled promise.” Media, Culture & Society
22.5 (2000): 531-556.
22.5 (2000): 531-556.
Browne, Nick. “The political economy of the
television (super) text.” Quarterly
Review of Film and Video 9.3
(1984): 174-182.
(1984): 174-182.
Carlson, Matt. “Tapping into TiVo”. New
Media & Society 8.1 (2006): 97-115.
Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema 2. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert
Galeta. Minneapolis, USA: University of Minnesota
Press, 1989.
Press, 1989.
Deleuze,
Gilles, and Felix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus. Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen Lane. Minneapolis,
USA: University of Minneapolis Press, 1983.
USA: University of Minneapolis Press, 1983.
Dienst,
Richard. Still Life In Real Time.
Durham, USA: Duke UP, 1994.
Doane, Mary
Ann. “The economy of desire: the Commodity form in/of the cinema” Quarterly
Review of Film and
Video 11.1 (1989): 23-33.
Video 11.1 (1989): 23-33.
Elsaesser, Thomas. The Persistence
of Hollywood. New York: Routledge 2012.
Genosko,
Gary. McLuhan and Baudrillard: the
masters of implosion. New York: Routledge, 1999.
Grossberg, Lawrence. “Mapping Popular Culture.” We Gotta Get Out of This Place. New York: Routledge, 1992.
Heidegger, Martin. “The Question Concerning Technology” The
Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.
Trans.William Lovitt. New York: Harper & Row, 1977. 3-35.
Trans.William Lovitt. New York: Harper & Row, 1977. 3-35.
Innis,
Harold. The Bias of Communication.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1951.
Kittler,
Friedrich. Gramophone, Film, Typewriter. Stanford, USA: Stanford UP, 1999.
Manovich,
Lev. The Language of New Media.
Cambridge, USA: The MIT Press, 2001.
Mattelart,
Armand. Networking the World, 1794-2000.
Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press, 2000.
McCarthy,
Anna. Ambient Television. Durham,
USA: Duke UP, 2001.
McLuhan,
Marshall. Understanding Media: the
Extensions of Man. Cambridge, USA: The MIT Press, 1994.
Metz,
Christian. Imaginary Signifier: Psychoanalysis and the Cinema. Bloomington, USA: Indiana UP, 1982.
--- “Photography and Fetish” October 34 (1985): 81-90.
--- “Photography and Fetish” October 34 (1985): 81-90.
Meyrowitz,
Joshua. "Mediating Communication: What Happens?." Questioning the Media. Ed. Downing et
al.
London: Sage, 1995. 39-53.
London: Sage, 1995. 39-53.
Mulvey, Laura. “Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema” Screen 16.3 (1975): 6-18.
Ong, Walter. Orality and Literacy. New
York: Routledge, 1982.
Schatz, Thomas. The Genius of the System.
London: Faber and Faber, 1998.
Spigel, Lynn. Make Room for TV. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992.
Uricchio, William. “Television’s
Next Generation: Technology/Interface Culture/Flow”. Television After TV. Ed. Lynn
Spigel and Jan Olsson. Durham, USA: Duke UP, 2004. 163-182.
Spigel and Jan Olsson. Durham, USA: Duke UP, 2004. 163-182.
Virilio, Paul. The Information Bomb. Trans. Chris Turner. London: Verso, 2000.
--- War and Cinema. Trans. Patrick Camiller. London: Verso, 1989.
--- War and Cinema. Trans. Patrick Camiller. London: Verso, 1989.
Williams.
Raymond. Television: Technology and
Cultural Form. New York: Routledge, 1990.
Žižek,
Slavoj. Organs Without Bodies. New
York: Routledge, 2004.
No comments:
Post a Comment